A Functional and Neuroanatomical Model of Dehumanization : Cognitive and Behavioral Neurology

Journal Logo

Opinion

A Functional and Neuroanatomical Model of Dehumanization

Mendez, Mario F. MD, PhD*,†,‡

Author Information
Cognitive and Behavioral Neurology 36(1):p 42-47, March 2023. | DOI: 10.1097/WNN.0000000000000316
  • Open

Abstract

Understanding dehumanization is important. Dehumanization is the act of depriving others of human qualities or demeaning their humanity. Excesses of dehumanization have had profoundly harmful consequences for targeted groups or individuals (Jack et al, 2013). People do not automatically attribute humanness to the same degree to all human beings (Haslam and Loughnan, 2014; Kteily et al, 2015), and subtle and unconscious dehumanization can lead to the debasement of groups or individuals (Harris and Fiske, 2006, 2007).

Otherwise normal people may deny positive human qualities, such as emotional warmth and competence, to certain individuals while experiencing these individuals as disgusting, less typically human, and more like animals (Harris and Fiske, 2006). At its most profound level, this type of dehumanization involves withholding empathy and moral protection from others, with the potential mistreatment of outgroups (Kteily et al, 2015). In addition to this form of dehumanization, normal people can also withhold humanness from others and treat them as indifferent objects through a failure to consider that they have minds containing thoughts and feelings, that is, mentalization (Harris and Fiske, 2011; Harris et al, 2007).

Neuroscience can contribute to understanding this important psychosocial phenomenon. Neurologists have long observed that dehumanization among people with frontally predominant neurologic dysfunction results in indifference to the humanness of others without experiencing them as disgusting or “animalistic.” The differences in dehumanization are a major clue to their neurobiological processes and, potentially, to mechanisms that can be used to modify this behavior (Figure 1).

F1
FIGURE 1:
Model of dehumanization and the brain. gACC = pregenual or subgenual anterior cingulate cortex. IFG = inferior frontal gyrus. VLPFC = ventrolateral prefrontal cortex. VMPFC = ventromedial prefrontal cortex.

“ANIMALISTIC” DEHUMANIZATION

Theoretical Background

Non–brain-injured or neurotypical subjects can manifest “infrahumanization,” or the perception of outgroup individuals as lacking unique human traits or emotions (Leyens et al, 2000). In addition to a perceived absence of positive human traits, such as social manners and cleanliness, infrahumanization theory states that primary and basic emotions shared with animals, such as fear and anger, are intact in outgroups as well as ingroups, but secondary or self-conscious emotions, such as guilt or shame, are less common in outgroups than in ingroups (Demoulin et al, 2004; Wilson and Haslam, 2013). Infrahumanization—by selectively denying others uniquely human secondary emotions but not basic ones—conceptualizes humanization in comparison with animals (Vaes et al, 2002). Haslam’s (2006) dual model of dehumanization further applies the term “animalistic dehumanization” to describe the disavowal of uniquely human traits, such as language and culture, and the devaluing of others as subhuman or nonhuman animals, resulting in feelings of disgust, use of animal epithets, and disdain toward outgroups (Goff et al, 2008).

Functional Mechanism

This form of dehumanization restrains empathy and emotional contagion when a person chooses, for example, to keep from empathizing with a destitute beggar or from considering another’s feelings in social hierarchies and dominance (Berthoz et al, 2006; Haidt, 2001, 2007; Ligneul et al, 2017; Moll et al, 2005). Dehumanization may result from the inhibition of tendencies to empathize when perceiving individuals of decreased physical or social status, including unattractiveness, facial disfigurement (Alaei et al, 2021; Cassidy et al, 2022; Hartung et al, 2019), and low socioeconomic status (Sainz et al, 2019).

An individual’s tendency to use animalistic dehumanization decreases the more the individual’s spatial and temporal features resemble the self (Hasson and Frith, 2016; Northoff and Huang, 2017; Scalabrini et al, 2019) and the more dissimilar those features are to those of animals, as suggested by electroencephalographic μ suppression in face-to-face dyadic interactions (Simon and Gutsell, 2021). In contrast, increased anthropomorphism, or extending human features to other animals or objects, may potentially increase animalistic dehumanization by blurring the human–animal boundary (Hortensius and Cross, 2018; Rottman et al, 2021). The “animalistic” nature of this dehumanization may relate to the status of animals as being lower than humans in the social order (Haslam and Loughnan, 2014).

Implicated Brain Regions

Several studies have implicated the ventrolateral prefrontal cortex (VLPFC), specifically the inferior frontal gyrus (IFG), as the source of this form of dehumanization. Neurobiological data suggest that the main role of the IFG in animalistic dehumanization is to inhibit prepotent positive emotional reactions to humans but not to animals (Aron et al, 2014a, 2014b; Swick et al, 2008). The IFG, especially on the right side, is involved in the “stop signal” inhibition of emotional contagion, the mirror neuron network, empathy, and risk aversion (Aron et al, 2003, 2014a, 2014b; Christopoulos et al, 2009; Iacoboni et al, 1999; Swick et al, 2008). This inhibition of positive, prosocial emotions may trigger the experience of disgust in the insula and amygdala. Furthermore, the VLPFC responds to social dominance cues and is engaged in rank perception (Qu et al, 2017): The left VLPFC/dorsal IFG responds to social hierarchy judgments (Farrow et al, 2011), and the right VLPFC responds to tasks of cooperation and competition and to cues of high social status (Liu et al, 2015; Marsh et al, 2009).

There may also be increased left IFG activity with animalistic and lower social status assessments (Bruneau et al, 2018). In contrast to its reaction to humans, the IFG may promote the anthropomorphism of animals and objects, suggesting a shift in positive emotions from humans (Gobbini et al, 2007). Increased right IFG activity occurs when resolving animate aspects of shapes (Cross et al, 2016). Viewing animals and humans engaging in animal-like behavior, as opposed to human behavior, results in greater activity in the left IFC as well as in other left lateralized brain regions (Jack et al, 2013).

“MECHANISTIC” DEHUMANIZATION

Theoretical Background

Haslam’s (2006) dual model of dehumanization distinguishes a second form of dehumanization that involves a perceived lack of a “typical” or essential human nature, such as having a mind with intentionality and agency (Harris et al, 2007; Haslam, 2006). This form of “mechanistic dehumanization,” by denying a mental life with thoughts, intentions, and an autonomous agency to others, devalues others as nonliving machines, resulting in feelings of indifference while seeing others as object-like, robotic, or alien (Haslam, 2006).

Functional Mechanism

The central characteristic of mechanical dehumanization is the failure to attribute mentalization to other human beings (Harris and Fiske, 2011; Haslam, 2006; Hortensius and Cross, 2018; Jack et al, 2013), resulting in the perception that they lack thoughts, feelings, and beliefs and, thus, do not warrant moral consideration (Harris and Fiske, 2006, 2011; Krumhuber et al, 2015; Waytz et al, 2010). People are viewed as human through the attribution of minds to them (Contini et al, 2020), and they reserve social cognitive resources for faces that have “attached” minds (Gray et al, 2007). Although humans can extend the capacity for mentalization to animals or to nonliving entities via anthropomorphism (Williams et al, 2020), people normally attribute full minds to humans.

Mechanistic dehumanization is a failure to perceive minds, perceiving them instead as just objects or machines. Mechanistic dehumanization thus objectifies others (Sainz et al, 2019)—a process that occurs among normal people in certain social encounters. For example, physicians may think of patients as “mechanical systems made up of interacting parts” that need repair (Haque and Waytz, 2012), and any corresponding lack of warmth and personal care of them reflects mechanistic dehumanization (Haque and Waytz, 2012; Haslam, 2006).

Implicated Brain Regions

Mechanistic dehumanization is associated with decreased mesial prefrontal activity involving the ventromedial prefrontal cortex (VMPFC) and the pregenual anterior cingulate cortex (gACC) (Harris and Fiske, 2006; Scalabrini et al, 2019), in addition to decreased parietal and default mode network function (Bruneau et al, 2018; Jack et al, 2013). The mesial frontal cortex appears to be the critical area for mentalization and for detecting valence and value from people but not objects. Decreased activity in the mesial frontal cortex, with a presumed denial of mentalization, has been associated with passively viewing images of people who are perceived as being low in warmth and competence (Harris and Fiske, 2006, 2007). Investigators have also reported decreased activity in brain areas for mentalizing and the use of fewer mental state verbs when considering people of low socioeconomic status (Harris and Fiske, 2006).

In addition to increased activity in the VMPFC during animate versus inanimate interactions, there is increased activity in the gACC, suggesting that this area is also critical for assessing the state of “livingness” in another human being (Scalabrini et al, 2019). In summary, dysfunction in both the VMPFC and the gACC may be responsible for mechanistic dehumanization and seeing people as objects or cold robots rather than humans.

EVIDENCE FROM BRAIN DISORDERS

Brain disorders, such as autism, frontal lobe trauma, frontal-predominant dementias, and Huntington disease, can cause mechanistic dehumanization but do not usually lead to animalistic dehumanization. Among these disorders, behavioral variant frontotemporal dementia (bvFTD) may best illustrate the effect of brain disease on dehumanization. Patients with bvFTD experience mechanistic dehumanization and are generally unemotional, unempathic, and indifferent to others, including the feelings of their family and friends (Rascovsky et al, 2011). However, these patients do not overtly devalue others or view them as disgusting.

The neuropathology of bvFTD is centered in the mesial frontal cortex (VMPFC, anterior cingulate cortex), frontal anterior insula, and anterior temporal lobe structures (Rosen et al, 2005; Seeley, 2008)—regions that are involved in mentalization. The affective component of mentalization is impaired early in bvFTD (Adenzato et al, 2010; Bora et al, 2015; Dodich et al, 2016; Henry et al, 2014; Orso et al, 2020; Pardini et al, 2013; Poletti et al, 2012, 2013; Torralva et al, 2015), and individuals with bvFTD exhibit decreased performance on moral dilemmas, where they do not foresee negative emotional reactions when contemplating directly harming others (Greene and Haidt, 2002; Greene et al, 2001). Furthermore, when viewing moving geometric shapes (Fong et al, 2017), individuals with bvFTD who have right IFG atrophy show significantly decreased anthropomorphization compared with controls. Additional evidence for impaired “humanness” perception is that individuals with frontotemporal dementia who are artists, specifically caricaturists, may draw others in a progressively distorted, nonhuman, or “alien” fashion as their dementia progresses (Mendez and Perryman, 2003). Finally, individuals with bvFTD express a seemingly paradoxical increased “presence” and interaction with avatars on virtual reality (Mendez et al, 2015), suggesting a blurred human–robot distinction.

CONCLUSION

There are two main mechanisms for dehumanization: restraint of prosocial emotions toward other humans in the IFG and impaired mentalization in the VMPFC and gACC. Both occur normally; however, only normal, non–brain-injured subjects demonstrate increased inhibition of prosocial emotions due to increased IFG activity, leading to animalistic dehumanization and disgust. People are normally responsive to others’ emotional experiences, and the IFG functions to restrain prepotent emotional contagion as well as complex emotions such as empathy for self-protection and hierarchical social ranking. It is this form of dehumanization, which promotes disgust of groups or individuals that are “flawed” and likens them to animals, that is linked to intergroup hostility and risk of violence (Kteily and Landry, 2022).

On the other hand, individuals with a brain injury may have disordered mentalization with a denial of full mind-attribution to others and mechanistic dehumanization with indifference. In contrast to individuals with animalistic dehumanization, individuals with mechanistic dehumanization do not show a tendency to blatantly dehumanize in an animalistic or infrahuman fashion. Mechanistic dehumanization may result from a decrease in the anterior network for mind-attribution or mentalization that is centered in the mesial frontal regions of the VMPFC and adjacent gACC.

These conclusions are a proposed model for dehumanization that is not definitively established and requires further research. Indeed, most of this paper involves the interpretation of neuroimaging studies that include relatively small numbers of subjects, and not all studies agree with the underlying cognitive processes involved and the role of the different frontal regions. Nevertheless, the profound importance of dehumanization behavior cries out for further theorizing and investigation of this concept.

Although dehumanized perception and biases are a fundamental part of our social cognition system and cannot be completely overcome, they can be moderated. The considerations described here should stimulate future research exploring these neurobiological mechanisms because they have the potential for behavioral and other interventions and preventative measures targeted at these proposed neurobiological mechanisms underlying dehumanization.

REFERENCES

Adenzato M, Cavallo M, Enrici I. 2010. Theory of mind ability in the behavioural variant of frontotemporal dementia: an analysis of the neural, cognitive, and social levels. Neuropsychologia. 48:2–12. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2009.08.001
Alaei R, Deska JC, Hugenberg K, et al. 2021. People attribute humanness to men and women differently based on their facial appearance. J Pers Soc Psychol. Published online June 24. doi: 10.1037/pspi0000364
Aron AR, Fletcher PC, Bullmore ET, et al. 2003. Stop-signal inhibition disrupted by damage to right inferior frontal gyrus in humans. Nat Neurosci. 6:115–116. doi: 10.1038/nn1003
Aron AR, Robbins TW, Poldrack RA. 2014a. Inhibition and the right inferior frontal cortex: one decade on. Trends Cogn Sci. 18:177–185. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2013.12.003
Aron AR, Robbins TW, Poldrack RA. 2014b. Right inferior frontal cortex: addressing the rebuttals. Front Hum Neurosci. 8:905. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2014.00905
Berthoz S, Grèzes J, Armony JL, et al. 2006. Affective response to one’s own moral violations. Neuroimage. 31:945–950. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2005.12.039
Bora E, Walterfang M, Velakoulis D. 2015. Theory of mind in behavioural-variant frontotemporal dementia and Alzheimer’s disease: a meta-analysis. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry. 86:714–719. doi: 10.1136/jnnp-2014-309445
Bruneau E, Jacoby N, Kteily N, et al. 2018. Denying humanity: the distinct neural correlates of blatant dehumanization. J Exp Psychol Gen. 147:1078–1093. doi: 10.1037/xge0000417
Cassidy BS, Wiley RW, Sim M, et al. 2022. Decoding complex emotions and humanization show related face processing effects. Emotion. 22:362–373. doi: 10.1037/3mo0000990
Christopoulos GI, Tobler PN, Bossaerts P, et al. 2009. Neural correlates of value, risk, and risk aversion contributing to decision making under risk. J Neurosci. 29:12574–12583. doi: 10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2614-09.2009
Contini EW, Goddard E, Grootswagers T, et al. 2020. A humanness dimension to visual object coding in the brain. Neuroimage. 221:117139. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2020.117139
Cross ES, Ramsey R, Liepelt R, et al. 2016. The shaping of social perception by stimulus and knowledge cues to human animacy. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 371:20150075. doi: 10.1098/rstb.2015.0075
Demoulin S, Leyens JP, Paladino MP, et al. 2004. Dimensions of “uniquely” and “non-uniquely” human emotions. Cogn Emot. 18:71–96. doi: 10.1080/02699930244000444
Dodich A, Cerami C, Crespi C, et al. 2016. Differential impairment of cognitive and affective mentalizing abilities in neurodegenerative dementias: evidence from behavioral variant of frontotemporal dementia, Alzheimer’s disease, and mild cognitive impairment. J Alzheimers Dis. 50:1011–1022. doi: 10.3233/JAD-150605
Farrow TF, Jones SC, Kaylor-Hughes CJ, et al. 2011. Higher or lower? The functional anatomy of perceived allocentric social hierarchies. Neuroimage. 57:1552–1560. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2011.05.069
Fong SS, Paholpak P, Daianu M, et al. 2017. The attribution of animacy and agency in frontotemporal dementia versus Alzheimer’s disease. Cortex. 92:81–94. doi: 10.1016/j.cortex.2017.03.019
Gobbini MI, Koralek AC, Bryan RE, et al. 2007. Two takes on the social brain: a comparison of theory of mind tasks. J Cogn Neurosci. 19:1803–1814. doi: 10.1162/jocn.2007.19.11.1803
Goff PA, Eberhardt JL, Williams MJ, et al. 2008. Not yet human: implicit knowledge, historical dehumanization, and contemporary consequences. J Pers Soc Psychol. 94:292–306. doi: 10.1037/0022-3514.94.2.292
Gray HM, Gray K, Wegner DM. 2007. Dimensions of mind perception. Science. 315:619. doi: 10.1126/science.1134475
Greene J, Haidt J. 2002. How (and where) does moral judgment work. Trends Cogn Sci. 6:517–523. doi: 10.1016/s1364-6613(02)02011-9
Greene JD, Sommerville RB, Nystrom LE, et al. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science. 293:2105–2108. doi: 10.1126/science.1062872
Haidt J. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol Rev. 108:814–834. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.108.4.814
Haidt J. 2007. The new synthesis in moral psychology. Science. 316:998–1002. doi: 10.1126/science.1137651
Haque OS, Waytz A. 2012. Dehumanization in medicine: causes, solutions, and functions. Perspect Psychol Sci. 7:176–186. doi: 10.1177/1745691611429706
Harris LT, Fiske ST. 2006. Dehumanizing the lowest of the low: neuroimaging responses to extreme out-groups. Psychol Sci. 17:847–853. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01793.x
Harris LT, Fiske ST. 2007. Social groups that elicit disgust are differentially processed in mPFC. Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci. 2:45–51. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsl037
Harris LT, Fiske ST. 2011. Dehumanized perception: a psychological means to facilitate atrocities, torture, and genocide? Z Psychol. 219:175–181. doi: 10.1027/2151-2604/a000065
Harris LT, McClure SM, van den Bos W, et al. 2007. Regions of the MPFC differentially tuned to social and nonsocial affective evaluation. Cogn Affect Behav Neurosci. 7:309–316. doi: 10.3758/cabn.7.4.309
Hartung F, Jamrozik A, Rosen ME, et al. 2019. Behavioural and neural responses to facial disfigurement. Sci Rep. 9:8021. doi: 10.1038/s41598-019-44408-8
Haslam N. 2006. Dehumanization: an integrative review. Pers Soc Psychol Rev. 10:252–264. doi: 10.1207/s15327957pspr1003_4
Haslam N, Loughnan S. 2014. Dehumanization and infrahumanization. Annu Rev Psychol. 65:399–423. doi: 10.1146/annurev-psych-010213-115045
Hasson U, Frith CD. 2016. Mirroring and beyond: coupled dynamics as a generalized framework for modelling social interactions. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci. 371:20150366.
Henry JD, Phillips LH, von Hippel C. 2014. A meta-analytic review of theory of mind difficulties in behavioural-variant frontotemporal dementia. Neuropsychologia. 56:53–62. doi: 10.1016/j.neuropsychologia.2013.12.024
Hortensius R, Cross ES. 2018. From automata to animate beings: the scope and limits of attributing socialness to artificial agents. Ann N Y Acad Sci. 1426:93–110. doi: 10.1111/nyas.13727
Iacoboni M, Woods RP, Brass M, et al. 1999. Cortical mechanisms of human imitation. Science. 286:2526–2528. doi: 10.1126/science.286.5449.2526
Jack AI, Dawson AJ, Norr ME. 2013. Seeing human: distinct and overlapping neural signatures associated with two forms of dehumanization. Neuroimage. 79:313–328. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2013.04.109
Krumhuber EG, Swiderska A, Tsankova E, et al. 2015. Real or artificial? intergroup biases in mind perception in a cross-cultural perspective. PLoS One. 10:e0137840. doi: 10.1371/journal.pone.0137840
Kteily N, Bruneau E, Waytz A, et al. 2015. The ascent of man: theoretical and empirical evidence for blatant dehumanization. J Pers Soc Psychol. 109:901–931. doi: 10.1037/pspp0000048
Kteily NS, Landry AP. 2022. Defining dehumanization broadly does not mean including everything. Trends Cogn Sci. 26:540–541. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2022.04.003
Leyens JP, Paladino PM, Rodriguez-Torres R, et al. 2000. The emotional side of prejudice: the attribution of secondary emotions to ingroups and outgroups. Pers Soc Psychol Rev. 4:186–197. doi: 10.1207/S15327957PSPR0402_06
Ligneul R, Girard R, Dreher JC. 2017. Social brains and divides: the interplay between social dominance orientation and the neural sensitivity to hierarchical ranks. Sci Rep. 7:45920. doi: 10.1038/srep45920
Liu T, Saito H, Oi M. 2015. Role of the right inferior frontal gyrus in turn-based cooperation and competition: a near-infrared spectroscopy study. Brain Cogn. 99:17–23. doi: 10.1016/j.bandc.2015.07.001
Marsh AA, Blair KS, Jones MM, et al. 2009. Dominance and submission: the ventrolateral prefrontal cortex and responses to status cues. J Cogn Neurosci. 21:713–724. doi: 10.1162/jocn.2009.21052
Mendez MF, Joshi A, Jimenez E. 2015. Virtual reality for the assessment of frontotemporal dementia, a feasibility study. Disabil Rehabil Assist Technol. 10:160–164. doi: 10.3109/17483107.2014.889230
Mendez MF, Perryman KM. 2003. Disrupted facial empathy in drawings from artists with frontotemporal dementia. Neurocase. 9:44–50. doi: 10.1076/neur.9.1.44.14375
Moll J, Zahn R, de Oliveira-Souza R, et al. 2005. Opinion: the neural basis of human moral cognition. Nat Rev Neurosci. 6:799–809. doi: 10.1038/nrn1768
Northoff G, Huang Z. 2017. How do the brain’s time and space mediate consciousness and its different dimensions? temporo-spatial theory of consciousness (TTC). Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 80:630–645. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2017.07.013
Orso B, Mattei C, Arnaldi D, et al. 2020. Clinical and MRI predictors of conversion from mild behavioural impairment to dementia. Am J Geriatr Psychiatry. 28:755–763. doi: 10.1016/j.jagp.2019.12.007
Pardini M, Gialloreti LE, Mascolo M, et al. 2013. Isolated theory of mind deficits and risk for frontotemporal dementia: a longitudinal pilot study. J Neurol Neurosurg Psychiatry. 84:818–821. doi: 10.1136/jnnp-2012-303684
Poletti M, Enrici I, Adenzato M. 2012. Cognitive and affective Theory of Mind in neurodegenerative diseases: neuropsychological, neuroanatomical and neurochemical levels. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 36:2147–2164. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2012.07.004
Poletti M, Lucetti C, Logi C, et al. 2013. Cognitive correlates of negative symptoms in behavioral variant frontotemporal dementia: implications for the frontal lobe syndrome. Neurol Sci. 34:1893–1896. doi: 10.1007/s10072-013-1400-2
Qu C, Ligneul R, Van der Henst JB, et al. 2017. An integrative interdisciplinary perspective on social dominance hierarchies. Trends Cogn Sci. 21:893–908. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2017.08.004
Rascovsky K, Hodges JR, Knopman D, et al. 2011. Sensitivity of revised diagnostic criteria for the behavioural variant of frontotemporal dementia. Brain. 134:2456–2477. doi: 10.1093/brain/awr179
Rosen HJ, Allison SC, Schauer GF, et al. 2005. Neuroanatomical correlates of behavioural disorders in dementia. Brain. 128:2612–2625. doi: 10.1093/brain/awh628
Rottman J, Crimston CR, Syropoulos S. 2021. Tree-huggers versus human-lovers: anthropomorphism and dehumanization predict valuing nature over outgroups. Cogn Sci. 45:e12967. doi: 10.1111/cogs.12967
Sainz M, Martínez R, Moya M, et al. 2019. Animalizing the disadvantaged, mechanizing the wealthy: the convergence of socio-economic status and attribution of humanity. Int J Psychol. 54:423–430. doi: 10.1002/ijop.12485
Scalabrini A, Ebisch SJ, Huang Z, et al. 2019. Spontaneous brain activity predicts task-evoked activity during animate versus inanimate touch. Cereb Cortex. 29:4628–4645. doi: 10.1093/cercor/bhy340
Seeley WW. 2008. Selective functional, regional, and neuronal vulnerability in frontotemporal dementia. Curr Opin Neurol. 21:701–707. doi: 10.1097/WCO.0b013e3283168e2d
Simon JC, Gutsell JN. 2021. Recognizing humanity: dehumanization predicts neural mirroring and empathic accuracy in face-to-face interactions. Soc Cogn Affect Neurosci. 16:463–473. doi: 10.1093/scan/nsab014
Swick D, Ashley V, Turken AU. 2008. Left inferior frontal gyrus is critical for response inhibition. BMC Neurosci. 9:102. doi: 10.1186/1471-2202-9-102
Torralva T, Gleichgerrcht E, Ardila MJ, et al. 2015. Differential cognitive and affective theory of mind abilities at mild and moderate stages of behavioral variant frontotemporal dementia. Cogn Behav Neurol. 28:63–70. doi: 10.1097/WNN.0000000000000053
Vaes J, Paladino MP, Leyens JP. 2002. The lost e-mail: prosocial reactions induced by uniquely human emotions. Br J Soc Psychol. 41:521–534. doi: 10.1348/014466602321149867
Waytz A, Gray K, Epley N, et al. 2010. Causes and consequences of mind perception. Trends Cogn Sci. 14:383–388. doi: 10.1016/j.tics.2010.05.006
Williams LA, Brosnan SF, Clay Z. 2020. Anthropomorphism in comparative affective science: advocating a mindful approach. Neurosci Biobehav Rev. 115:299–307. doi: 10.1016/j.neubiorev.2020.05.014
Wilson SG, Haslam N. 2013. Humanness beliefs about behavior: an index and comparative human-nonhuman behavior judgments. Behav Res Methods. 45:372–382. doi: 10.3758/s13428-012-0252-7
Keywords:

dehumanization; mentalization; anthropomorphism; frontotemporal dementia